History, Reviews, Science.

The Origins of Modern Science

Book Book Review, Title The Origins of Modern Science, Author Herbert Butterfield, Rating 4.0,

Herbert Butterfield, in his book The Origins of Modern Science, constructs a history of science from the late Middle Ages until the advent of the French Revolution, with primary emphasis on the development of the modern understanding of motion. This is a brilliant choice, as it was a robust physical and mathematical model of motion that allowed Newton to unite terrestrial and astronomical physics into a universal set of physical laws describing mechanics.

Having come across many references to this book in scientific histories, I decided to re-read it.  This book was one of the texts for a class in the History of Science I took many years ago at Oregon State University.  It has much still to recommend it.

-CC by 3.0, Portolanero

Ptolemy with armillary sphere. Attrib: Portolanero, CC by 3.0.

Butterfield provides an excellent summary of the ancient Greek physical models upon which first Arab scholars, then medieval Western thinkers employed to bring some understanding of both the sublunary sphere (terrestrial), summarized and synthesized by Aristotle, and the remaining spheres (astronomical), summarized and synthesized by Ptolemy.  The ultimate failure of both of these models and their ultimate replacement with a unified view came from the increased emphasis on experimentation and more critically, the employment of mathematical models to the explanation of physical phenomena.  The author points out that exploring Nature through experimentation was not suppressed by Muslim or medieval academics, but was less prominent than it became in the burgeoning modern scientific method, particularly as promoted by Francis Bacon with his strong emphasis on empiricism.

Butterfield suggests that Galileo and Descartes both had large roles in the birth of modern science in their employment of mathematical and geometrical models to to explain and explore the physics of terrestrial and astronomical motion.

Galileo heavily influenced the future employment of the scientific method, not only in his use of more rigorous experimentation in validating ideas, but in particular his attempts to measure time intervals more accurately.  The older Greek ideas about time were murky, based more on the psychological perception of time as something that was variable.  Galileo, in his early experiments with a simple gravity pendulum, found that the period of the pendulum was consistent and essentially constant, which to Galileo suggested that time was not variable, but regular, and from that he developed time-measuring devices from pendulums to facilitate his measurements of objects in motion.

-PD-US,

Galileo Galilei, 1636, by Sustermans. PD-US.

Perhaps one of the most difficult, and thereby amazing, changes in thinking about motion came with the development of the concept of inertia.  Galileo is usually credited with first developing the idea, as he did, but not to the degree of freeing the concept of motion from the old Aristotelian physics.  Galileo’s idea of inertia was defined to solve problems of orbital mechanics; he applied it only to circular motion in attempting to understand the paths of planets and moons.  Galileo did not relinquish the old Aristotelian ideas of motion terrestrially.

Descartes was able to refine this idea of inertia into the more general understanding that Newton adopted, and which is truly modern:  A body in motion moves in a straight line and continues with the same momentum unless it is acted upon by some other agency or force.  Descartes developed the basic idea of the conservation of momentum from which this conception of inertia was deduced, and which was the grandfather of the various conservation laws of modern science.

-PD-US,

René Descartes, by Frans Hals. Le Louvre. PD-US.

However, Descartes himself was unable to extricate his thinking entirely from the Aristotelian physical model.  It is from Aristotle that the phrase Nature abhors a vacuum arises, and underpins the Aristotelian idea that no action can be initiated from a distance.  Aristotle insisted that an object changes its motion only under the direct influence of another object or substance, and that space was filled, in some way or other, with material substances that allowed the direct propagation of forces that modified the motion of an object.  Descartes built an elaborate deductive description of Nature based on this Aristotelian concept, historically and scientifically a blind alley.  Butterfield suggests that Descarte’s ultimate limitation was to rely too little on mathematical modeling and direct observation and too much on the powers of logical deduction.

-PD-US, Inst. Math. Sci., U. of Cambridge

Isaac Newton, 1689, by Godfrey Kneller. Attrib: Inst. Math. Sci., U. of Cambridge, PD-US.

Newton’s grand synthesis of terrestrial and astronomical mechanics was built on his deceptively simple three Laws of Motion, each inherited in part from his predecessors.  These laws were placed in a world alien ultimately to all who preceded him:  An absolute framework of three-dimensional space, mostly empty, with time treated as a steady and precise beat by which all events marched ever forward.  His development of the Universal Law of Gravitation completed the tie between terrestrial and astronomical physics, with all objects in the universe attracting each other in a precise way, such that the behavior of the motion of cannonballs and the motion of the planets could be described using the same rules.  Butterfield opined that 

Both Descartes and Newton were in the first rank of geometers; but the ultimate victory of Newton has a particular significance for us in that it vindicated the alliance of geometry with the experimental method against the elaborate deductive system of Descartes. The clean and comparatively empty Newtonian skies ultimately carried the day against a Cartesian universe packed with matter and agitated with whirlpools, for the existence of which scientific observation provided no evidence.
-Chapter 8 (page 170)
 

There is much more on the specifics of modern scientific origins, including some discussion of the early development of biology, evolution, chemistry and optics, and additional coverage of the emergence of the Copernican heliocentric model of the solar system.

Butterfield’s treatment of history follows somewhat von Ranke’s approach; he is wary of overstating the effect of leading ideas, of too quickly employing the pithily summarized ideas as stereotypical concepts, and in particular of ignoring both the role of human proclivities and the unwieldy swirl of change that permeates human history. (Butterfield is less convinced by von Ranke’s heavy insistence on empiricism and the goal of representing history as it actually happened.)  He points out repeatedly that the main ideas of early science were developed from many, often inextricable influences, be they societal, religious, political, academic and so on.

As Arthur Koestler pointed out in The Sleepwalkers, and as can be seen with Galileo’s and Descarte’s efforts, useful and even brilliant things were discovered or constructed within the ultimately discarded framework of the old Greek philosophical models; in another example, Kepler’s desire to extend the Ptolemaic model using the simplest geometrical models drove him to search, in vain, for a heliocentric model based on the geometry of the perfect solids, but in the process, he discovered his three Laws of Planetary Motion, which were finally absorbed into the Newtonian synthesis.  No one thread of explanation suffices to explain adequately the origins of modern science. Newton’s own view of the world was a mix of the radical modern elements for which he is celebrated, and the more currently accepted and unscientific ideas; he spent years of research in the areas of numerology, alchemy and Christian theology.

Butterfield, a Christian historian, finished by saying of science that 

Our Graeco-Roman roots and our Christian heritage were so profound - so central to our thinking - that it has required centuries of pulls and pressures, and almost a conflict of civilizations in our very midst, to make clear that the center had long ago shifted. At one time the effects of the scientific revolution, and the changes contemporary with it, would be masked by the persistence of our classical traditions and education . . . At another time these effects would be concealed through that popular attachment to religion which so helped to form the character of even the 19th century in Britain . . . (Modern science) as a new factor immediately began to elbow the other ones away, pushing them back from their central position . . . the result was the emergence of a civilization . . . that could cut itself away from its Graeco-Roman heritage in general, away from Christianity itself - only too confident in its power to exist independent of anything of the kind. We know now that what was emerging towards the end of the seventeenth century was a civilization exhilaratingly new perhaps, but strange as Nineveh and Babylon. That is why, since the rise of Christianity, there is no landmark in history that is worthy to be compared with this.
-Chapter 10 (page 201)
 

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Solve the puzzle to post a comment *